Elections, contributions: the right to participate in democracy through
political contributions is protected by the First Amendment, but that right is
not absolute. Congress may regulate campaign contributions to protect against
corruption or the appearance of corruption. See, e.g., Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U. S. 1, 26–27. It may not, however, regulate contributions simply to
reduce the amount of money in politics, or to restrict the political
participation of some in order to enhance the relative influence of others.
See, e.g., Arizona Free Enterprise Club’s Freedom Club PAC v. Bennett,
564 U. S. ___, ___. The Federal Election Campaign Act of 1971 (FECA), as
amended by the Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002 (BCRA), imposes two types
of limits on campaign contributions. Base limits restrict how much money a
donor may contribute to a particular candidate or committee while aggregate
limits restrict how much money a donor may contribute in total to all
candidates or committees. 2 U. S. C. §441a. In the 2011–2012 election cycle,
appellant McCutcheon contributed to 16 different federal candidates, complying
with the base limits applicable to each. He alleges that the aggregate limits
prevented him from contributing to 12 additional candidates and to a number of
noncandidate political committees. He also alleges that he wishes to make
similar contributions in the future, all within the base limits. McCutcheon and
appellant Republican National Committee filed a complaint before a three-judge
District Court, asserting that the aggregate limits were unconstitutional
under the First Amendment. The District Court denied their motion for a
preliminary injunction and granted the Government’s motion to dismiss. Assuming
that the base limits appropriately served the Government’s anticorruption interest,
the District Court concluded that the aggregate limits survived First
Amendment scrutiny because they prevented evasion of the base limits.
Held: The judgment is reversed, and
the case is remanded. 893 F. Supp. 2d 133, reversed and remanded. CHIEF JUSTICE
ROBERTS, joined by JUSTICE SCALIA, JUSTICE KENNEDY, and JUSTICE ALITO,
concluded that the aggregate limits are invalid under the First
Amendment.
(a) Appellants’ substantial First Amendment challenge
to the current system of aggregate limits merits plenary consideration.
(1) In Buckley, this Court evaluated the
constitutionality of the original contribution and expenditure limits in FECA. Buckley
distinguished the two types of limits based on the degree to which each
encroaches upon protected First Amendment interests. It subjected expenditure
limits to “the exacting scrutiny applicable to limitations on core First
Amendment rights of political expression.” 424 U. S., at 44–45. But it
concluded that contribution limits impose a lesser restraint on political
speech and thus applied a lesser but still “rigorous standard of review,” id.,
at 29, under which such limits “may be sustained if the State demonstrates
a sufficiently important interest and employs means closely drawn to avoid
unnecessary abridgement of associational freedoms,” id., at 25. Because
the Court found that the primary purpose of FECA—preventing quid pro quo corruption
and its appearance—was a “sufficiently important” governmental interest, id.,
at 26–27, it upheld the base limit under the “closely drawn” test, id., at
29. After doing so, the Court devoted only one paragraph of its 139-page
opinion to the aggregate limit then in place under FECA, noting that the
provision “had not been separately addressed at length by the parties.” Id.,
at 38. It concluded that the aggregate limit served to prevent
circumvention of the base limit and was “no more than a corollary” of that
limit. Id., at 38.
(2) There is no need in this case to revisit Buckley’s
distinction between contributions and expenditures and the corresponding distinction
in standards of review. Regardless whether strict scrutiny or the “closely
drawn” test applies, the analysis turns on the fit between the stated
governmental objective and the means selected to achieve that objective. Here,
given the substantial mismatch between the Government’s stated objective and
the means selected to achieve it, the aggregate limits fail even under the
“closely drawn” test.
Buckley’s ultimate conclusion about the
constitutionality of the aggregate limit in place under FECA does not control
here. Buckley spent just three sentences analyzing that limit, which had
not been separately addressed by the parties. Appellants here, by contrast,
have directly challenged the aggregate limits in place under BCRA, a different
statutory regime whose limits operate against a distinct legal backdrop. Most
notably, statutory safeguards against circumvention have been considerably
strengthened since Buckley. The 1976 FECA Amendments added another layer
of base limits—capping contributions from individuals to political
committees—and an antiproliferation rule prohibiting donors from creating or
controlling multiple affiliated political committees. Since Buckley,
the Federal Election Commission has also enacted an intricate regulatory scheme
that further limits the opportunities for circumvention of the base limits
through “unearmarked contributions to political committees likely to
contribute” to a particular candidate. 424 U. S., at 38. In addition to
accounting for such statutory and regulatory changes, appellants raise
distinct legal arguments not considered in Buckley, including an
overbreadth challenge to the aggregate limit.
(b) Significant First Amendment interests are
implicated here. Contributing money to a candidate is an exercise of an
individual’s right to participate in the electoral process through both
political expression and political association. A restriction on how many
candidates and committees an individual may support is hardly a “modest
restraint” on those rights. The Government may no more restrict how many
candidates or causes a donor may support than it may tell a newspaper how many
candidates it may endorse. In its simplest terms, the aggregate limits prohibit
an individual from fully contributing to the primary and general election
campaigns of ten or more candidates, even if all contributions fall within the
base limits. And it is no response to say that the individual can simply
contribute less than the base limits permit: to require one person to
contribute at lower levels because he wants to support more candidates or
causes is to penalize that individual for “robustly exercising” his First
Amendment rights. Davis v. Federal Election Comm’n, 554 U. S.
724, 739. In assessing the First Amendment interests at stake, the proper focus
is on an individual’s right to engage in political speech, not a collective
conception of the public good. The whole point of the First Amendment is to
protect individual speech that the majority might prefer to restrict, or that
legislators or judges might not view as useful to the democratic process.
(c) The aggregate limits do not further the
permissible governmental interest in preventing quid pro quo corruption
or its appearance.
(1) This Court has identified only one legitimate
governmental interest for restricting campaign finances: preventing corruption
or the appearance of corruption. See Davis,
supra, at 741. Moreover, the only type of corruption that Congress may
target is quid pro quo corruption. Spending large sums of money in
connection with elections, but not in connection with an effort to control the
exercise of an officeholder’s official duties, does not give rise to quid
pro quo corruption. Nor does the possibility that an individual who spends
large sums may garner “influence over or access to” elected officials or political
parties. Citizens United v. Federal Election Comm’n, 558 U. S.
310, 359. The line between quid pro quo corruption and general influence
must be respected in order to safeguard basic First Amendment rights, and the
Court must “err on the side of protecting political speech rather than
suppressing it.” Federal Election Comm’n v. Wisconsin Right to Life,
551 U. S. 449, 457 (opinion of ROBERTS, C. J.).
(2) The Government argues that the aggregate limits
further the permissible objective of preventing quid pro quo corruption.
The difficulty is that once the aggregate limits kick in, they ban all
contributions of any amount, even though Congress’s selection of a base
limit indicates its belief that contributions beneath that amount do not create
a cognizable risk of corruption. The Government must thus defend the aggregate
limits by demonstrating that they prevent circumvention of the base limits, a
function they do not serve in any meaningful way. Given the statutes and
regulations currently in effect, Buckley’s fear that an individual
might “contribute massive amounts of money to a particular candidate through .
. . unearmarked contributions” to entities likely to support the candidate,
424 U. S., at 38, is far too speculative. Even accepting Buckley’s
circumvention theory, it is hard to see how a candidate today could receive
“massive amounts of money” that could be traced back to a particular donor
uninhibited by the aggregate limits. The Government’s scenarios offered in
support of that possibility are either illegal under current campaign finance
laws or implausible.
(3) The aggregate limits also violate the First
Amendment because they are not “closely drawn to avoid unnecessary abridgment
of associational freedoms.” Buckley, supra, at 25. The
Government argues that the aggregate limits prevent an individual from giving
to too many initial recipients who might then recontribute a donation, but
experience suggests that the vast majority of contributions are retained and
spent by their recipients. And the Government has provided no reason to
believe that candidates or party committees would dramatically shift their
priorities if the aggregate limits were lifted. The indiscriminate ban on all
contributions above the aggregate limits is thus disproportionate to the
Government’s interest in preventing circumvention.
Importantly, there are multiple alternatives available
to Congress that would serve the Government’s interest in preventing circumvention
while avoiding “unnecessary abridgment” of First Amendment rights. Buckley,
supra, at 25. Such alternatives might include targeted restrictions on
transfers among candidates and political committees, or tighter earmarking
rules. Transfers, after all, are the key to the Government’s concern about
circumvention, but they can be addressed without such a direct and broad
interference with First Amendment rights.
(4) Disclosure of contributions also reduces the
potential for abuse of the campaign finance system. Disclosure requirements,
which are justified by “a governmental interest in ‘providing the electorate
with information’ about the sources of election-related spending,” Citizens
United, supra, at 367, may deter corruption “by exposing large
contributions and expenditures to the light of publicity,” Buckley, supra
at 67. Disclosure requirements may burden speech, but they often represent
a less restrictive alternative to flat bans on certain types or quantities of
speech. Particularly with modern technology, disclosure now offers more robust
protections against corruption than it did when Buckley was decided.
(d) The Government offers an additional rationale for
the aggregate limits, arguing that the opportunity for corruption exists
whenever a legislator is given a large check, even if the check consists of contributions
within the base limits to be divided among numerous candidates or committees.
That rationale dangerously broadens the circumscribed definition of quid
pro quo corruption articulated in prior cases. Buckley confined its
analysis to the possibility that “massive amounts of money” could be funneled
to a particular candidate in excess of the base limits. 424 U. S., at
38. Recasting as corruption a donor’s widely distributed support for a
political party would dramatically expand government regulation of the
political process. And though the Government suggests that solicitation of
large contributions poses the corruption danger, the aggregate limits are not
limited to any direct solicitation by an officeholder or candidate.
JUSTICE THOMAS agreed that the aggregate limits are
invalid under the First Amendment, but would overrule Buckley v. Valeo,
424 U. S. 1, and subject BCRA’s aggregate limits to strict scrutiny, which they
would surely fail. Buckley’s “analytic foundation . . . was tenuous from
the very beginning and has only continued to erode in the intervening years.” Nixon
v. Shrink Missouri Government PAC, 528 U. S. 377, 412 (THOMAS, J.,
dissenting). Contributions and expenditures are simply “two sides of the same
First Amendment coin,” and this Court’s efforts to distinguish the two have
produced mere “word games” rather than any cognizable constitutional law
principle. Buckley, supra, at 241, 244 (Burger, C. J., concurring
in part and dissenting in part). (U.S.S.Ct., 02.04.2014, McCutcheon v. Federal
Election Comm’n, Docket 12-536, C.J. Roberts).
Contributions
financières aux candidats à des élections fédérales : le droit de
participer au processus démocratique par des contributions politiques est
protégé par le Premier Amendement de la Constitution fédérale. Ce droit n’est
pas absolu. Le Congrès fédéral peut légiférer le système des contributions dans
le cadre des campagnes électorales pour parer la corruption ou son apparence
(cf. jurisprudence Buckley). Il ne peut toutefois pas légiférer en matière de
contributions seulement pour réduire le montant total des sommes investies dans
le domaine politique, ni seulement pour restreindre la participation politique
de certains en vue d’augmenter l’influence relative d’autres. Les deux lois
fédérales électorales principales prévoient deux types de limites s’agissant
des contributions financières dans les campagnes électorales. La limite dite de
base restreint le montant qu’un donateur peut allouer à un candidat ou à un
comité électoral. La limite combinée, de son côté, restreint les montants qu’un
donateur peut allouer à l’ensemble des candidats et des comités électoraux.
Dans cette affaire, la cour de district fédérale juge que la limite combinée
est conforme au Premier Amendement du fait qu’elle prévient le contournement de
la législation sur la limite de base, laquelle n’est pas en cause.
La Cour
Suprême fédérale annule ce jugement de première instance, et déclare que la
législation sur la limite combinée est contraire au Premier Amendement.
Dans sa
jurisprudence Buckley, la Cour ne consacre qu’un paragraphe à la question de la
limite combinée, jugeant qu’elle est un corollaire de la limite de base, en ce
qu’elle permet d’éviter le contournement de la limite de base, la législation relative
à cette dernière étant jugée conforme à la Constitution.
La présente
espèce n’implique nullement de revoir la distinction opérée par la
jurisprudence Buckley entre contributions et dépenses d’une part, et entre les
deux standards qui leurs sont applicables respectivement, d’autre part. Que
l’on applique l’un ou l’autre des deux standards (« strict scrutiny »
ou « closely drawn »), la question en dernière analyse est celle de
la relation entre l’objectif gouvernemental allégué (par exemple prévenir la
corruption dans le champ électoral) et les moyens sélectionnées pour atteindre
cet objectif. Dans cette affaire, la dichotomie entre l’intérêt gouvernemental
allégué et les moyens pour l’atteindre, la législation sur la limite combinée
n’est pas conforme à la Constitution.
La présente
espèce ne remet en cause que le principe de la législation sur la limite
combinée et non celle sur la limite de base. La question de la limite combinée
n’a pratiquement pas été abordée par Buckley.
Des intérêts
significatifs relevant du Premier Amendement sont ici en jeu : une
donation à un candidat dans le cadre d’une campagne électorale constitue pour
une personne l’exercice de son droit individuel à participer au processus
électoral à la fois par expression politique et par association politique.
Une
restriction portant sur le nombre de candidats et de comités électoraux qu’un
individu peut soutenir n’est guère une restriction modeste aux droits en
matière électorale. Le Gouvernement n’est pas non plus autorisé à prescrire à
un journal combien de candidats il est en droit de soutenir. En résumé, la
législation sur la limite combinée interdit à un individu de contribuer
pleinement aux campagnes des élections primaire et générale lorsque sont en
lice 10 candidats ou davantage, même si l’ensemble de ses contributions
respectent la limite de base. On ne saurait soutenir à ce niveau qu’il suffit
pour le donateur de verser des montants inférieurs à la limite de base pour
pouvoir soutenir davantage de candidats. Pratiquer ainsi reviendrait à
pénaliser le droit de la personne à exercer ses droits découlant du Premier
Amendement de manière énergique (« robustly »).
La législation
sur la limite combinée n’est pas adéquate pour concrétiser l’intérêt admissible
du Gouvernement à prévenir la corruption ou son apparence.
La Cour n’a
identifié qu’un intérêt gouvernemental légitime pour limiter les contributions
financières dans les campagnes électorales : prévenir la corruption ou
l’apparence de celle-ci. Par ailleurs, contribuer par de larges sommes ne veut
encore pas dire vouloir contrôler l’action du parlementaire élu, de sorte que
l’apparence de corruption n’est pas réalisée du seul fait de dépenser de larges
sommes dans la campagne électorale. La possibilité qu’un donateur qui dépense
d’importantes sommes pourrait ainsi influencer l’élu n’est pas en soi un fait
établi.
D’autre part,
la notion de limite combinée viole aussi le premier Amendement parce qu’elle
n’est pas précisément cadrée pour éviter sans nécessité des restrictions à la
liberté d’association. L’interdiction sans aucune distinction de toutes les
contributions au-dessus de la limite combinée est disproportionnée en
comparaison avec l’intérêt gouvernemental à prévenir le contournement de la
législation électorale.
Il est
important de remarquer que le Congrès dispose de multiples alternatives
susceptibles de servir l’intérêt du Gouvernement à prévenir ce contournement,
tout en évitant des restrictions sans nécessité des droits découlant du Premier
Amendement, telle par exemple une réglementation des restrictions de transferts
parmi les candidats et les comités politiques.
Par ailleurs, la publication des contributions réduit également le
potentiel d’abus du système de financement des campagnes électorales. Des
obligations de publications, justifiées par un intérêt gouvernemental à
procurer à l’électorat des informations relatives aux sources des dépenses
liées aux élections, peuvent prévenir la corruption en exposant
publiquement aussi bien les larges
contributions que les dépenses importantes. Des obligations de publicité
peuvent porter atteinte à la liberté d’expression, mais elles représentent
souvent une alternative d’une nature moins restrictive que de simples
interdictions de certains types ou de certaines « quantité »
d’expression. Particulièrement grâce à la technologie moderne, la publication
maintenant offre une protection plus robuste contre la corruption qu’à l’époque
où a été rendue la jurisprudence Buckley.
Le Juge Thomas
est lui aussi d’avis que la législation sur la limite combinée ne résiste pas
au Premier Amendement. Mais il souhaiterait en plus renverser la décision
Buckley v. Valeo. Selon lui, les contributions et les dépenses ne sont que les
deux faces de la même pièce soumise au Premier Amendement, et, toujours selon
lui, les efforts de la Cour pour les distinguer n’ont produit que des jeux de
mots, au lieu de principes de droit constitutionnel compréhensibles.
No comments:
Post a Comment